The American Philosopher: Conversations with Quine, Davidson, Putnam, Nozick, Danto, Rorty, Cavell, MacIntyre, Kuhn

Front Cover
University of Chicago Press, 2008 M04 15 - 192 pages
In this lively look at current debates in American philosophy, leading philosophers talk candidly about the changing character of their discipline. In the spirit of Emerson's The American Scholar, this book explores the identity of the American philosopher. Through informal conversations, the participants discuss the rise of post-analytic philosophy in America and its relations to European thought and to the American pragmatist tradition. They comment on their own intellectual development as well as each others' work, charting the course of American philosophy over the past few decades.

Giovanna Borradori, in her substantial introduction, explains the history of the analytic movement in America and the home-grown reaction against it. In the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, American philosophy was a socially engaged interdisciplinary enterprise. In transcendentalism and pragmatism, then the dominant currents in American thought, philosophy was connected to history, psychology, and public issues. But in the 1930s, the imported European movement of logical positivism redefined philosophical discourse in terms of mathematical logic and theory of language. Under the influence of this analytic view, American philosophy became a professionalized discipline, divorced from public debate and intellectual history and antagonistic to the other, more humanistic tradition of continental thought.

The American Philosopher explores the opposition between analytic and continental thought and shows how recent American work has begun to bridge the gap between the two traditions. Through a reexamination of pragmatism, and through an attempt to understand philosophy in a more hermeneutical way, the participants narrow the distance between America's distinctly scientific philosophy and Europe's more literary approach.

Moving beyond classical analytic philosophy, the participants confront each other on a number of topics. The logico-linguistic orientations of Quine and Davidson come up against the more discursive, interdisciplinary agendas of Rorty, Putnam, and Cavell. Nozick's theory of pluralist anarchism goes face-to-face with the aesthetic neo-foundationalism of Danto. And Kuhn's hypothesis of paradigm shifts is measured against MacIntyre's ethics of "virtues."

Borradori's conversations offer an unconventional portrait of the way philosophers think about their work; scholars and students will not be its only beneficiaries, so will everyone who wonders about the current state of American philosophy.

From inside the book

Contents

The Atlantic Wall
1
Willard Van Orman Quine
27
Donald Davidson
40
Hilary Putnam
55
Robert Nozick
70
Arthur C Danto
86
Richard Rorty
103
Stanley Cavell
118
Alasdair MacIntyre
137
Thomas S Kuhn
153
Index
169
Copyright

Other editions - View all

Common terms and phrases

Popular passages

Page 112 - If in hermeneutics you include "weak thought," which I am familiar with, we have to be clear about it. Neither Dewey nor weak thought imply that history is on our side, or that there is any necessary force that's going to cause a good outcome. On the contrary, there are nine chances out of ten that things will go to hell. However, what is important is the hope that they might not end badly, because they are not fated to go one way or the other.
Page 10 - A fellowship at the Center for the Critical Analysis of Contemporary Culture at Rutgers University sensitized me to cultural perspectives.
Page 140 - ... knew still belonged with part of themselves. What mattered in this culture were particular loyalties and ties to kinship and land. To be just was to play one's assigned role in the life of one's local community. Each person's identity derived from the person's place in their community and in the conflicts and arguments that constituted its ongoing (or by the time of my childhood no longer ongoing) history.
Page 151 - I am not a communitarian. I do not believe in ideals or forms of community as a nostrum for contemporary social ills. I give my political loyalty to no program" (Borradori, The American Philosopher, 151).
Page 64 - Putnam says that for him (and Dewey) democracy is a "cognitive value" insofar as it is "a requirement for experimental inquiry in any area. To reject democracy is to reject the idea of being experimental.
Page 36 - The way I look at things today is that there isn't only one science, but a big enough bundle of laws not to be comprehended as a single hypothesis. The big enough bundle implies logically some observational conditions,9 namely some categories defining observable situations ... holism is needed to the extent that you have a big enough combination to apply some of these testable categories (Borradori. 1994, p. 36). The theme...
Page 107 - Americans simply had not produced anything in philosophy for a long time. Dewey's best work had been written before 1925, hence for twenty-five years not much had happened in American philosophy — though Dewey was still alive and revered. In the thirties, the German and Austrian emigres began coming over — people like Carnap, Hempel, Tarski, Reichenbach — and, after the Second World War, they simply took over American philosophy departments. They were an explicidy anti-historicist movement,...
Page 114 - I think that deconstruction is an American product. God only knows what it is, it is a very loosely used term. It really applies more to Paul de Man than to Derrida, but a de Manian literary criticism, as far as I know, simply does not exist. However, because we have a hundred thousand professors of English in America, it is part of the training in graduate school. How would you define the difference between "deconstruction" and "textualism," the very successful term you coined in Consequences of...

About the author (2008)

Giovanna Borradori has taught philosophy at Milan Polytechnic and Vassar College. She is the editor of Recoding Metaphysics: The New Italian Philosophy and the author of Il Pensiero Post-Filosofico. Currently she lives in New York City.

Bibliographic information